Why People Make Bad DecisionsWednesday, June 24, 2009 at 09:08 AM EDT
A while ago, when I wrote a
review of Freakonomics, I got a comment
from a reader who made it quite clear that they didn’t think I knew
the hell what I was talking about: “As for rationality. People
don’t make decisions rationally, or for that matter irrationally. Just
not how we’re wired.â€
I think that Cian is sort-of
right, and I don’t think that Cian being sort-of right means that
I’m totally wrong. It’s not a zero-sum game. Most people make
most
of their decisions in the hope of achieving the best outcome – but
because the amount of social, economic and cultural data to be parsed is too
huge for most people to survey, many decisions come out pretty eccentric.
“Our brains work like big coincidence detectors and use improbable
coincidences to make decisions about what is realâ€, as psychologist
Tom Stafford explained. If a coincidence is neither big enough nor
improbable enough, it may not register at all.
MMR is a good example. From a medical outcome point of view, the rational
decision would be to take the jab and have done. But what if you’ve been
made aware of the vaccine damage hypothesis, but have no experience of the
diseases the vaccine is protecting against? Then you might be more fearful of
the vaccine than the disease, and the rational response to that (however
irrational the data) would be to avoid vaccination.

And what if non-vaccination had some other benefits that don’t show
up
in the epidemiology? Like a
powerful feeling of community with other anti-vaxxers and a belief that you are
part of an important narrative of repressed knowledge? Those social factors
could be very powerful incentives, and might push the decision-maker firmly
away from vaccines.
Why am I dwelling on a months-old blog comment today? (Hint: not just
because I am slow-brained and resentful of correction.) Because I came
across two excellent blog posts lately which used analogies with irrational
economics to rationalise apparently illogical behaviours.
Tom
Ewing parses some data on boom-and-bust in baby names:
the rapid spikes of popularity and unpopularity in some baby
names look very much like the inflation and bursting of market bubbles. And the
driver of unpopularity is the sudden increase in perceived risk (social risk,
in this case). Would it be true to say that the more people’s
‘network perception’ plays a role in decision making, the more
likely rapid popularity spikes are?
Blackbeard
Blog, “Baby bubblesâ€
Aaronovitch Watch compares David Aaronovitch’s ongoing apologia for
the Iraq war to the behaviour of a scam victim:
What clearly went on in 2002 was either that there was
intentional deception, or that the government believed that Saddam had WMDs,
and therefore because it believed this, thought it was a gamble worth taking to
portray the evidence as much more conclusive than it was. That’s the
sort
of thing that people go to jail for if they do it in a set of accounts; if this
isn’t “lyingâ€, then there were no liars in the executive
suite at Enron.
Aaro himself, notoriously, was persuaded by the government case to make a
massive investment of credibility points into a decidedly subprime vehicle (the
parallels between the September dossier, in which poor quality underlying
material was layered, structured and given the imprimateur of a supposedly
neutral agency to create the illusion of AAA status, and the CDO market, are
perhaps fertile ground for someone more desperate for a column than myself).
Unlike the investors in Bernard Madoff’s funds, however, he seems
determined to defend the very people who swindled him. Nice one.
Aaronovitch
Watch, “What is this, the missing chapter of Voodoo
Histories?â€
To which the only thing I feel like adding is that people quite often
continue to poor funds into a duff investment they’ve been persuaded to
make, because the social cost of admitting the mistake seems greater than the
financial cost of continuing it. Similarly, the social cost of changing your
child’s name is usually even greater than the cost of sticking with
something that’s turned out to be a bit common. Even irrationality can
have a rational outcome.
|